Skip to document

Business Ethics B5 Advertising

Grade A+
Course

Applied Business and Management Ethics (MAG-44)

25 Documents
Students shared 25 documents in this course
Academic year: 2021/2022
Uploaded by:
Anonymous Student
This document has been uploaded by a student, just like you, who decided to remain anonymous.
Riverside City College

Comments

Please sign in or register to post comments.

Preview text

GALBRAITH AND GRANOLA: ETHICAL ISSUES IN ADVERTISING

Firms rely heavily on their ability to successfully advertise, market, and eventually sell products and services. After all, it is the responsibility of those working in these areas to help ensure that there are actually people to do business with— that there are a sufficient number of customers who both (1) know about the products or services offered by the firm and (2) think that these products or services represent a worthwhile use of their money. Ethical issues begin to arise, however, when firms use their expertise in these areas to subtly deceive or coerce potential customers in order to make a profit. This may involve dishonest advertising, “hard sell” techniques, the targeting of vulnerable groups (such as children, those with mental illness, etc.), or similar techniques. In this lesson we’ll be looking at question regarding both personal morality (what are the responsibility of an individual working in an advertising agency?) and public policy (what sorts of behavior should FCC, FDA, and other government agencies actually prohibit or allow? ).

GALBRAITH AND “THE DEPENDENCE EFFECT”

“As a society becomes increasingly affluent, wants are increasingly created by the process by which they are satisfied.... Wants thus come to depend on output. In technical terms, it can no longer be assumed that welfare is greater at an all-round higher level of production than at a lower one. It may be the same. The higher level of production has, merely, a higher level of want creation necessitating a higher level of want satisfaction. There will be frequent occasion to refer to the way wants depend on the process by which they are satisfied. It will be convenient to call it the Dependence Effect.” (J. Galbraith, The Affluent Society )

One of the most important modern critics of advertising was John Kenneth Galbraith (1908- 2006), a Canadian-American economist who served in the FDR, JFK, and LBJ Democratic administrations (he also wrote a number of popular books on economics). His critique of neoclassical economics was strongly informed by the earlier work of the Minnesota economist Thorstein Veblen (1857-1929), who had written about the economic phenomena of conspicuous consumption (people are motivated to buy luxury goods in order that other people can see them consuming these goods.)

Like Veblen, Galbraith focused on the particular ways that free markets could fail to promote wellbeing, and on possibility of designing effective institutions to help correct these imbalances. Galbraith argues in particular that the nature of modern advertising and marketing requires a much greater deal of government intervention than is sometimes thought. The basic argument:

The Neoclassical Case for Free Markets. According to neoclassical economic theory, free and competitive markets help to maximize the well-being of citizens’ by creating a tight link between match between the quantity of goods demanded by consumers (we can call these the consumer’s wants ), and quantity of goods supplied by producers. It helps ensure that those consumers with the strongest wants are the ones who get it (since markets award good to the highest bidder). Over time, competition between producers will increase the degree to which products meet consumer’s demands AND will drive down costs. The basic idea is this: citizens want things, and a good society should do what it can to maximize the extent to which they get these things (a version of utilitarianism). Since free markets are the best way of ensuring this, we should have free markets!

Importantly, the models of classical economics assume a few things: that consumers have complete information regarding the products they purchase, that they will choose rationally, and that their desires/wants are independent of the market (e., they knew what they wanted before they came to the market). While neoclassical economists recognized that no market perfectly met these criteria, they nevertheless thought it was a good approximation. On the version of this view that Galbraith critiques, advertising simply serve to remedy customer’s lack of knowledge, and thus makes our imperfect markets closer to the ideal market.

Granolaville, Pt. 1: The consumers of town Granolaville all have a strong desire for granola. Currently, there are ten manufacturers of cereal in the town, but none offer granola. In response, the customers choose the cereals that most closely approximate granola. The producers (slowly) respond and, eventually, the customers have ten brands of granola to choose from. Competition improves quality and reduces cost, and everyone is as happy as can be (at least with respect to breakfast cereal...). Advertising, in this society, serves exactly one role: to help inform the consumers about the changes that have been made to the cereal (“Now even more like granola!”). It thus helps markets function more efficiently, and raises no moral problems.

When Free Markets Fail: The Dependence Effect. Galbraith does NOT claim that neoclassical models are “wrong,” but he thinks they don’t always apply to modern markets in the way they did when the neoclassical theorists first formulated them. In particular, he argues that, through advertising and marketing, modern firms help to create the very wants they satisfy. Importantly, this “dependence” of wants upon production means that the earlier argument for the value of free markets fail, since this was based on the idea that markets were merely a way of satisfying preexisting wants, and not of creating wants that (when unfulfilled) could actually make people less happy. This doesn’t mean that the effects of advertising are all negative, of course (ads still play an important role in informing customers, entertaining people, employing creative types, and so on). The problem with this, according to Galbraith, is that this distorts markets in unhealthy ways, since consumers will be motivated to spend their resources pursuing these “new” wants, when they could more productively be devoted to “public” goods (infrastructure, education, parks, and so on). Democratic elections, by themselves, can’t fix this problem, since people’s voting choices will be heavily informed by the advertising to which they have been exposed. (Recent research on happiness has provided some support for Galbraith—materialistic people who consume more unnecessary “luxuries” really do get short-term benefits from doing so, but they are also unhappier than materialistic people in the long run).

Granola Example, Pt. 2. The granola firms, unsatisfied with their market share, begin aggressive marketing campaigns. Some make implausible health claims (“You’ll lose twenty pounds if you eat this! And that’s important!!”), and encourage a sense of body insecurity formerly lacking in Granolaville. Others appeal to classism (“Eat our fancy granola! Which poor people can’t afford, so everyone will know you are rich!”), or direct their advertising children (“Free toys! Extra sugar!”). Some play on fear (“Eat all-natural! Our rival’s brands will turn you into a zombie!”), while others attach themselves to beloved sports teams, public buildings, and even school curricula. The Granolaville residents become unhealthy and spiteful, and begin spending their excess funds on fancier granola, at the expense of public services like education and infrastructure. Consumers continue to buy the latest and greatest granola, but many people find themselves stressed and unhappy.

Solving the Problem? Well there isn’t space to dive into Galbraith’s proposals in detail, he argues that there is a significantly greater role for the public sector (i. government) to play in

desires and the way that contemporary marketing does. Finally, even if successful, Hayek’s argument doesn’t show that advertising is beneficial (or that it shouldn’t be regulated), merely that Galbraith’s criticisms of it need revision. There’s been a fair amount of empirical research into the question of how happiness relates to consumers’ spending habits relate to their happiness in recent years, with scholars finding that happiness is correlated with both low levels of materialism, and with high level of perceived autonomy.

WRAPPING UP: LEGAL AND MORAL RESTRICTIONS ON ADVERTISING

Galbraith and Hayek are largely focused on the role that government ought to play in responding to the problems raised by advertising and marketing. Galbraith holds that there is a significant role for the government to play, while Hayek thinks there is much less of a role. Neither theorist offers any specific guidance on how this ought to apply to individuals, however. With this in mind, it’s worth considering a few issues more directly relevant to those working within advertising:

“Legally OK” does not entail “morally OK.” On both Galbraith’s and Hayek’s view, advertising serves a variety of purposes: informing consumers of new products, driving innovation and growth, and helping customers identify reasons to favor one product over another. Advertising also plays a key role in funding television, radio, web sites, etc. For all these reasons, government needs to be careful in restricting advertising. For example, while the government might be justified in banning fraudulent advertising or in restricting advertising aimed at children, it can’t plausibly eliminate all instance of “puffery” (exaggerating how great a product is), or ban ads appealing to our “worse” emotions (vanity, greed, fear, etc.). However, this does not mean that individual firms shouldn’t be concerned about these things.

What Separates Morally OK Ads from Immoral Ones? The ethicist Alan Goldman argues that “the basic [moral] principle regarding effects of persuasion is that advertisers ought not to create desires whose fulfillment would be more harmful than beneficial to consumers. More broadly, the principle we propose would prohibit encouraging irrational desires.” There is, for example, something clearly morally reprehensible about ads aimed at selling products that firms know (or should have known) will harm their customers (whether these be cigarettes, fad diets, etc.). This principle entails that companies ought to especially cautious when marketing to children, since they are especially susceptible to emotion-based appeals. So, for example, where there may be nothing (morally) wrong with advertising violent movies or unhealthy foods for adults (since adults should be capable of understanding what’s go on), these same ads may raise concerns when targeted to children.

Putting Advertising to Good Work? In recent years, a number of behavioral economists have begun investigating the precise ways in which people are (predictably) irrational. Among other things, we do very badly when trying to account for low-probability, high-impact events; we hate things described as “losses” more than we love things described as “gains”; we place far too much emphasis on first impressions, and other things. While those working in advertising and marketing have long had a good “feel” for these things, behavioral economists have begun encouraging non-

Figure 1 Apu puts behavioral economics to work. (From i sdoi i h del )

profit and governmental organizations (especially those involved in issues such as public health) to begin utilizing these strategies, as well. The idea, in short, is to craft advertising/marketing materials that actually help people become more rational when it comes to making decisions regarding personal finance, health, and education. This view is sometimes called libertarian paternalism, as it supposedly blends parts of Galbraith’s “paternalism” (the government directly makes choices on people’s behalf) and Hayek’s “libertarianism” (people make their own choices). There are worries from both sides, however. Traditional left-wing liberals worry that direct action may be more effective, while traditional right-wing libertarians think it is a misuse of government funds. Both groups sometimes express worries that it is “manipulative” in a way that more straightforward government programs are not. (Finally, there are worries over whether this even works! As it turns out, people are fairly resistant to “nudges” encouraging them to become more healthy, save more money, etc.).

REVIEW QUESTIONS

  1. In your own words, describe Galbraith’s and Hayek’s debate over the effects of advertising, and the proper government response to it. Whose view (if either) do you think is more correct? Why?
  2. Some recent ad campaigns and marketing decisions that have been criticized on ethical grounds include the following. Do a little research, explain why there is a controversy, and say whether you think it is justified: a. Is it ethical for fashion magazines to (disproportionately) run photos of thin models, and to make widespread use of airbrushing/graphic design software to further alter their appearance? b. Is it ethical for internet uses to routinely use “Ad block” software, which may make it more difficult for the site they visit to stay finically viable? c. Should there be greater restrictions place on the advertising of unhealthy food (fast food, candy), especially where this marketing seems to be aimed at children? d. Some other recent issue you know about that relates to advertising.
  3. What do you think of the ideas behind “libertarian paternalism”? Is this something you’d like to see the government (and/or non-profits such health insurance companies or hospitals) make more use of? Why or why not?

REFERENCES AND BIBLIOGRAPHY

 Arrington, Robert L. 1982. “Advertising and Behavior Control.” Journal of Business Ethics 1 (1): 3–12.  Dutt, Amitava Krishna. 2008. “The Dependence Effect, Consumption and Happiness: Galbraith Revisited.” Review of Political Economy 20 (4): 527–50. doi:10/09538250802308919.  Galbraith, John Kenneth. 1998. The Affluent Society. 40 Anv Sub edition. Boston: Mariner Books.  Hayek, Friedrich A. 1961. “The Non Sequitur of the‘ Dependence Effect.’” Southern Economic Journal , 346–48.  Laczniak, Gene R., and Patrick E. Murphy. 2006. “Normative Perspectives for Ethical and Socially Responsible Marketing.” Journal of Marketing 26: 154.  Veblen, Thorstein. 1997. The Theory of the Leisure Class. gutenberg/ebooks/833.

Was this document helpful?

Business Ethics B5 Advertising

Course: Applied Business and Management Ethics (MAG-44)

25 Documents
Students shared 25 documents in this course
Was this document helpful?
GALBRAITH AND GRANOLA: ETHICAL ISSUES IN ADVERTISING
Firms rely heavily on their ability to successfully advertise, market, and eventually sell products
and services. After all, it is the responsibility of those working in these areas to help ensure that
there are actually people to do business with—that there are a sufficient number of customers who
both (1) know about the products or services offered by the firm and (2) think that these products
or services represent a worthwhile use of their money. Ethical issues begin to arise, however,
when firms use their expertise in these areas to subtly deceive or coerce potential customers in
order to make a profit. This may involve dishonest advertising, “hard sell” techniques, the
targeting of vulnerable groups (such as children, those with mental illness, etc.), or similar
techniques. In this lesson we’ll be looking at question regarding both personal morality (what are
the responsibility of an individual working in an advertising agency?) and public policy (what sorts
of behavior should FCC, FDA, and other government agencies actually prohibit or allow?).
GALBRAITH AND THE DEPENDENCE EFFECT
As a society becomes increasingly affluent, wants are increasingly created
by the process by which they are satisfied.... Wants thus come to depend on
output. In technical terms, it can no longer be assumed that welfare is greater
at an all-round higher level of production than at a lower one. It may be the
same. The higher level of production has, merely, a higher level of want
creation necessitating a higher level of want satisfaction. There will be
frequent occasion to refer to the way wants depend on the process by which
they are satisfied. It will be convenient to call it the Dependence Effect.” (J.K.
Galbraith, The Affluent Society)
One of the most important modern critics of advertising was John Kenneth Galbraith (1908-
2006), a Canadian-American economist who served in the FDR, JFK, and LBJ Democratic
administrations (he also wrote a number of popular books on economics). His critique of
neoclassical economics was strongly informed by the earlier work of the Minnesota economist
Thorstein Veblen (1857-1929), who had written about the economic phenomena of
conspicuous consumption (people are motivated to buy luxury goods in order that other people
can see them consuming these goods.)
Like Veblen, Galbraith focused on the particular ways that free markets could fail to promote
wellbeing, and on possibility of designing effective institutions to help correct these imbalances.
Galbraith argues in particular that the nature of modern advertising and marketing requires a
much greater deal of government intervention than is sometimes thought. The basic argument:
The Neoclassical Case for Free Markets. According to neoclassical economic theory, free and
competitive markets help to maximize the well-being of citizens’ by creating a tight link between
match between the quantity of goods demanded by consumers (we can call these the consumer’s
wants), and quantity of goods supplied by producers. It helps ensure that those consumers with
the strongest wants are the ones who get it (since markets award good to the highest bidder).
Over time, competition between producers will increase the degree to which products meet
consumer’s demands AND will drive down costs. The basic idea is this: citizens want things, and a
good society should do what it can to maximize the extent to which they get these things (a
version of utilitarianism). Since free markets are the best way of ensuring this, we should have
free markets!